Friday 24 April 2015

Juris North: Legal and Political Philosophy Discussion Group [CALL FOR PRESENTERS]


 
 
Juris North, a legal and political philosophy discussion group, in collaboration with the Universities of Birmingham, Durham, Hull, Liverpool, Manchester, and Manchester Metropolitan.

 

Call for Presenters 2015-16

If your current research is on a topic that can be broadly characterised as jurisprudence—i.e. legal and political philosophy, and you would be interested in presenting it to a friendly group, which includes academics as well as lawyers, you are welcome to be a presenter at the Juris North Discussion Group.

The discussions are normally held on Wednesday afternoons. But we can be flexible about the particular days that we meet. Discussions are always informal and very lively since we follow a Rawlsian approach. That means we do not have “Professors” and “Students” but people interested in discussing issues related to legal and political philosophy. So any question is an important question for debate.

If you would like to give a paper as part of our 2015-16 Working Paper Series then please send an abstract, no more than 500 words long and written in English. If you are interested, please contact Dr Jorge Emilio Nunez j.nunez@mmu.ac.uk.

The seminars will have a ‘pre-read’ format: successful applicants will be asked to send a draft paper two weeks in advance of the seminar so that it can be circulated amongst members of the group.

Accommodation and expenses: we will not be able to make any contribution towards accommodation and travel expenses.

 

Enquiries please contact Dr Jorge Núñez: j.nunez@mmu.ac.uk

 

Friday 17 April 2015

The Force of Law: Law and Coercion, Validity and Effectiveness, and Synergy


The Force of Law:

Law and Coercion, Validity and Effectiveness, and Synergy[1]

 

JORGE EMILIO NUNEZ

 
Abstract This paper considers the two claims Schauer introduces in The Force of Law. Firstly, the paper seeks to establish that coercion is (a) generally part of the law; and (b) occasionally may be not. Secondly, I intend to demonstrate that despite the fact that the relationship between rules and facts within a normative system could be necessary, sufficient or desirable, in all cases is a synergetic one: they outperform when they work together. Therein, the last section of this paper shows that coercion has philosophical interest in explaining the nature of law since the question whether it is a necessary or sufficient element is irrelevant.

 Available at SSRN: SSRN Link One or SSRN Link Two


[1] A very early version of this paper “нормативные системы как право в синергии: ДЕЙСТВИТЕЛЬНОСТЬ И ДЕЙСТВЕННОСТЬ” (in English, “Normative Systems as Law in Synergy: Validity and Effeciveness”), Philosophy of Law and State Responsibility, St. Petersburg State University, 2012.



Saturday 11 April 2015

The Force of Law


At last, some sense in legal philosophy. With circular and already-answered-from-the-start discussions for decades about whether a quest in understanding the nature of law—i.e. what is law?—should include coercion, it is The Force of Law that reignites the enquiry long ago thought to be settled. Schauer has two intertwined claims: a) that law is commonly and valuably coercive; and b) a challenge to a prevalent mode of jurisprudence inquiry.
 
 

With regards the former, Schauer tells us that “[l]aw makes us do things we do not want to do […] [and] unlike morality and etiquette, possesses the resources to compel compliance in ways that other normative systems do not […]. [For instance], the law has sanctions at its disposal that are systematic, often severe, and highly salient. The legal system can put us in prison, take our money, and in some places even flog us and kill us”. But, for over fifty years legal theory, following H.L.A. Hart has made an assumption that law cannot be identified with force. Indeed, “[t]he theory of law as coercive order meets at the outset with the objection that there are varieties of law found in all systems which, in three principal respects, do not fit this description.” Therein, an opinion translated into dogma: law may refer to coercion but it does not need to by default—i.e. coercion is not a necessary condition for law to be.

Schauer agrees that “noncoercive law both can and does exist.” That is not the issue he intends to unravel in The Fore of Law. However, because we currently understand in legal philosophy that coercion is not a necessary condition for law to be, and legal philosophy seems to be interested only in those features in law that are considered essential, “coercion loses its philosophical or theoretical interest in explaining the nature of law”. And that is Schauer’s second claim, that legal philosophy or legal theory should not be limited to search for essential features, elements, or components.

There are already voices against Schauer’s attempt to reintroduce coercion as a more starring character within law. In his latest paper, Leslie Green “addresses the question of the relationship between law and coercive force”. Green makes, against Frederick Schauer’s claims in his book, The Force of Law, the following points:

“(a) The force of law consists in three things, not one: the imposition of duties, the use of coercion, and the exercise of social power
; (b) Even if coercion is not part of the concept of law, coercion is connected to law in a variety of ways. These are amply recognized in contemporary jurisprudence; [and] (c) We cannot determine how important coercion is to the efficacy of law until we know what counts as coercive force. This question is not a matter for empirical generalization or bare stipulation. It requires an explanation of the concept of coercion. […] Before we can count we need to know that what counts as what. Counting—as is a matter of identifying necessary and sufficient conditions.”
 
 
Despite the apparent disagreements, the focus of this literature, however, is largely on the question of the justifiability of including coercion amongst the elements to be studied when referring to the nature of law. There is a huge literature on the elements that constitute the law. Within this literature, and in particular since Hart’s The Concept of Law, coercion in not central to this study. To be more precise, coercion is only briefly noted as a potential, additional and apparently optional element in this literature, rather than being subject to detailed analysis.